home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- (For more information about the GNU project and free software,
- look at the files `GNU', `COPYING', and `DISTRIB', in the same
- directory as this file.)
-
-
- Why Software Should Be Free
-
- by Richard Stallman
-
- (Version of April 24, 1992)
-
- Copyright (C) 1991, 1992, Free Software Foundation, Inc.
- Verbatim copying and redistribution is permitted
- without royalty; alteration is not permitted.
-
- Introduction
- ************
-
- The existence of software inevitably raises the question of how
- decisions about its use should be made. For example, suppose one
- individual who has a copy of a program meets another who would like a
- copy. It is possible for them to copy the program; who should decide
- whether this is done? The individuals involved? Or another party,
- called the "owner"?
-
- Software developers typically consider these questions on the
- assumption that the criterion for the answer is to maximize developers'
- profits. The political power of business has led to the government
- adoption of both this criterion and the answer proposed by the
- developers: that the program has an owner, typically a corporation
- associated with its development.
-
- I would like to consider the same question using a different
- criterion: the prosperity and freedom of the public in general.
-
- This answer cannot be decided by current law--the law should conform
- to ethics, not the other way around. Nor does current practice decide
- this question, although it may suggest possible answers. The only way
- to judge is to see who is helped and who is hurt by recognizing owners
- of software, why, and how much. In other words, we should perform a
- cost-benefit analysis on behalf of society as a whole, taking account of
- individual freedom as well as production of material goods.
-
- In this essay, I will describe the effects of having owners, and show
- that the results are detrimental. My conclusion is that programmers
- have the duty to encourage others to share, redistribute, study and
- improve the software we write: in other words, to write "free"
- software.(1)
-
- How Owners Justify Their Power
- ******************************
-
- Those who benefit from the current system where programs are property
- offer two arguments in support of their claims to own programs: the
- emotional argument and the economic argument.
-
- The emotional argument goes like this: "I put my sweat, my heart, my
- soul into this program. It comes from *me*, it's *mine*!"
-
- This argument does not require serious refutation. The feeling of
- attachment is one that programmers can cultivate when it suits them; it
- is not inevitable. Consider, for example, how willingly the same
- programmers usually sign over all rights to a large corporation for a
- salary; the emotional attachment mysteriously vanishes. By contrast,
- consider the great artists and artisans of medieval times, who didn't
- even sign their names to their work. To them, the name of the artist
- was not important. What mattered was that the work was done--and the
- purpose it would serve. This view prevailed for hundreds of years.
-
- The economic argument goes like this: "I want to get rich (usually
- described inaccurately as `making a living'), and if you don't allow me
- to get rich by programming, then I won't program. Everyone else is like
- me, so nobody will ever program. And then you'll be stuck with no
- programs at all!" This threat is usually veiled as friendly advice
- from the wise.
-
- I'll explain later why this threat is a bluff. First I want to
- address an implicit assumption that is more visible in another
- formulation of the argument.
-
- This formulation starts by comparing the social utility of a
- proprietary program with that of no program, and then concludes that
- proprietary software development is, on the whole, beneficial, and
- should be encouraged. The fallacy here is in comparing only two
- outcomes--proprietary software vs. no software--and assuming there are
- no other possibilities.
-
- Given a system of intellectual property, software development is
- usually linked with the existence of an owner who controls the
- software's use. As long as this linkage exists, we are often faced
- with the choice of proprietary software or none. However, this linkage
- is not inherent or inevitable; it is a consequence of the specific
- social/legal policy decision that we are questioning: the decision to
- have owners. To formulate the choice as between proprietary software
- vs. no software is begging the question.
-
- The Argument against Having Owners
- **********************************
-
- The question at hand is, "Should development of software be linked
- with having owners to restrict the use of it?"
-
- In order to decide this, we have to judge the effect on society of
- each of those two activities *independently*: the effect of developing
- the software (regardless of its terms of distribution), and the effect
- of restricting its use (assuming the software has been developed). If
- one of these activities is helpful and the other is harmful, we would be
- better off dropping the linkage and doing only the helpful one.
-
- To put it another way, if restricting the distribution of a program
- already developed is harmful to society overall, then an ethical
- software developer will reject the option of doing so.
-
- To determine the effect of restricting sharing, we need to compare
- the value to society of a restricted (i.e., proprietary) program with
- that of the same program, available to everyone. This means comparing
- two possible worlds.
-
- This analysis also addresses the simple counterargument sometimes
- made that "the benefit to the neighbor of giving him or her a copy of a
- program is cancelled by the harm done to the owner." This
- counterargument assumes that the harm and the benefit are equal in
- magnitude. The analysis involves comparing these magnitudes, and shows
- that the benefit is much greater.
-
- To elucidate this argument, let's apply it in another area: road
- construction.
-
- It would be possible to fund the construction of all roads with
- tolls. This would entail having toll booths at all street corners.
- Such a system would provide a great incentive to improve roads. It
- would also have the virtue of causing the users of any given road to
- pay for that road. However, a toll booth is an artificial obstruction
- to smooth driving--artificial, because it is not a consequence of how
- roads or cars work.
-
- Comparing free roads and toll roads by their usefulness, we find that
- (all else being equal) roads without toll booths are cheaper to
- construct, cheaper to run, safer, and more efficient to use.(2) In a
- poor country, tolls may make the roads unavailable to many citizens.
- The roads without toll booths thus offer more benefit to society at
- less cost; they are preferable for society. Therefore, society should
- choose to fund roads in another way, not by means of toll booths. Use
- of roads, once built, should be free.
-
- When the advocates of toll booths propose them as *merely* a way of
- raising funds, they distort the choice that is available. Toll booths
- do raise funds, but they do something else as well: in effect, they
- degrade the road. The toll road is not as good as the free road; giving
- us more or technically superior roads may not be an improvement if this
- means substituting toll roads for free roads.
-
- Of course, the construction of a free road does cost money, which the
- public must somehow pay. However, this does not imply the inevitability
- of toll booths. We who must in either case pay will get more value for
- our money by buying a free road.
-
- I am not saying that a toll road is worse than no road at all. That
- would be true if the toll were so great that hardly anyone used the
- road--but this is an unlikely policy for a toll collector. However, as
- long as the toll booths cause significant waste and inconvenience, it is
- better to raise the funds in a less obstructive fashion.
-
- To apply the same argument to software development, I will now show
- that having "toll booths" for useful software programs costs society
- dearly: it makes the programs more expensive to construct, more
- expensive to distribute, and less satisfying and efficient to use. It
- will follow that program construction should be encouraged in some other
- way. Then I will go on to explain other methods of encouraging and (to
- the extent actually necessary) funding software development.
-
- The Harm Done by Obstructing Software
- =====================================
-
- Consider for a moment that a program has been developed, and any
- necessary payments for its development have been made; now society must
- choose either to make it proprietary or allow free sharing and use.
- Assume that the existence of the program and its availability is a
- desirable thing.(3)
-
- Restrictions on the distribution and modification of the program
- cannot facilitate its use. They can only interfere. So the effect can
- only be negative. But how much? And what kind?
-
- Three different levels of material harm come from such obstruction:
-
- * Fewer people use the program.
-
- * None of the users can adapt or fix the program.
-
- * Other developers cannot learn from the program, or base new work
- on it.
-
- Each level of material harm has a concomitant form of psychosocial
- harm. This refers to the effect that people's decisions have on their
- subsequent feelings, attitudes and predispositions. These changes in
- people's ways of thinking will then have a further effect on their
- relationships with their fellow citizens, and can have material
- consequences.
-
- The three levels of material harm waste part of the value that the
- program could contribute, but they cannot reduce it to zero. If they
- waste nearly all the value of the program, then writing the program
- harms society by at most the effort that went into writing the program.
- Arguably a program that is profitable to sell must provide some net
- direct material benefit.
-
- However, taking account of the concomitant psychosocial harm, there
- is no limit to the harm that proprietary software development can do.
-
- Obstructing Use of Programs
- ===========================
-
- The first level of harm impedes the simple use of a program. A copy
- of a program has nearly zero marginal cost (and you can pay this cost by
- doing the work yourself), so in a free market, it would have nearly zero
- price. A license fee is a significant disincentive to use the program.
- If a widely-useful program is proprietary, far fewer people will use it.
-
- It is easy to show that the total contribution of a program to
- society is reduced by assigning an owner to it. Each potential user of
- the program, faced with the need to pay to use it, may choose to pay,
- or may forego use of the program. When a user chooses to pay, this is a
- zero-sum transfer of wealth between two parties. But each time someone
- chooses to forego use of the program, this harms that person without
- benefitting anyone. The sum of negative numbers and zeros must be
- negative.
-
- But this does not reduce the amount of work it takes to *develop*
- the program. As a result, the efficiency of the whole process, in
- delivered user satisfaction per hour of work, is reduced.
-
- This reflects a crucial difference between copies of programs and
- cars, chairs, or sandwiches. There is no copying machine for material
- objects outside of science fiction. But programs are easy to copy;
- anyone can produce as many copies as are wanted, with very little
- effort. This isn't true for material objects because matter is
- conserved: each new copy has to be built from raw materials in the same
- way that the first copy was built.
-
- With material objects, a disincentive to use them makes sense,
- because fewer objects bought means less raw materials and work needed
- to make them. It's true that there is usually also a startup cost, a
- development cost, which is spread over the production run. But as long
- as the marginal cost of production is significant, adding a share of the
- development cost does not make a qualitative difference. And it does
- not require restrictions on the freedom of ordinary users.
-
- However, imposing a price on something that would otherwise be free
- is a qualitative change. A centrally-imposed fee for software
- distribution becomes a powerful disincentive.
-
- What's more, central production as now practiced is inefficient even
- as a means of delivering copies of software. This system involves
- enclosing physical disks or tapes in superfluous packaging, shipping
- large numbers of them around the world, and storing them for sale. This
- cost is presented as an expense of doing business; in truth, it is part
- of the waste caused by having owners.
-
- Damaging Social Cohesion
- ========================
-
- Suppose that both you and your neighbor would find it useful to run a
- certain program. In ethical concern for your neighbor, you should feel
- that proper handling of the situation will enable both of you to use it.
- A proposal to permit only one of you to use the program, while
- restraining the other, is divisive; neither you nor your neighbor should
- find it acceptable.
-
- Signing a typical software license agreement means betraying your
- neighbor: "I promise to deprive my neighbor of this program so that I
- can have a copy for myself." People who make such choices feel
- internal psychological pressure to justify them, by downgrading the
- importance of helping one's neighbors--thus public spirit suffers.
- This is psychosocial harm associated with the material harm of
- discouraging use of the program.
-
- Many users unconsciously recognize the wrong of refusing to share, so
- they decide to ignore the licenses and laws, and share programs anyway.
- But they often feel guilty about doing so. They know that they must
- break the laws in order to be good neighbors, but they still consider
- the laws authoritative, and they conclude that being a good neighbor
- (which they are) is naughty or shameful. That is also a kind of
- psychosocial harm, but one can escape it by deciding that these licenses
- and laws have no moral force.
-
- Programmers also suffer psychosocial harm knowing that many users
- will not be allowed to use their work. This leads to an attitude of
- cynicism or denial. A programmer may describe enthusiastically the
- work that he finds technically exciting; then when asked, "Will I be
- permitted to use it?", his face falls, and he admits the answer is no.
- To avoid feeling discouraged, he either ignores this fact most of the
- time or adopts a cynical stance designed to minimize the importance of
- it.
-
- Since the age of Reagan, the greatest scarcity in the United States
- is not technical innovation, but rather the willingness to work together
- for the public good. It makes no sense to encourage the former at the
- expense of the latter.
-
- Obstructing Custom Adaptation of Programs
- =========================================
-
- The second level of material harm is the inability to adapt programs.
- The ease of modification of software is one of its great advantages over
- older technology. But most commercially available software isn't
- available for modification, even after you buy it. It's available for
- you to take it or leave it, as a black box--that is all.
-
- A program that you can run consists of a series of numbers whose
- meaning is obscure. No one, not even a good programmer, can easily
- change the numbers to make the program do something different.
-
- Programmers normally work with the "source code" for a program, which
- is written in a programming language such as Fortran or C. It uses
- names to designate the data being used and the parts of the program, and
- it represents operations with symbols such as `+' for addition and `-'
- for subtraction. It is designed to help programmers read and change
- programs. Here is an example; a program to calculate the distance
- between two points in a plane:
-
- float
- distance (p0, p1)
- struct point p0, p1;
- {
- float xdist = p1.x - p0.x;
- float ydist = p1.y - p0.y;
- return sqrt (xdist * xdist + ydist * ydist);
- }
-
- Here is the same program in executable form, on the computer I
- normally use:
-
- 1314258944 -232267772 -231844864 1634862
- 1411907592 -231844736 2159150 1420296208
- -234880989 -234879837 -234879966 -232295424
- 1644167167 -3214848 1090581031 1962942495
- 572518958 -803143692 1314803317
-
- Source code is useful (at least potentially) to every user of a
- program. But most users are not allowed to have copies of the source
- code. Usually the source code for a proprietary program is kept secret
- by the owner, lest anybody else learn something from it. Users receive
- only the files of incomprehensible numbers that the computer will
- execute. This means that only the program's owner can change the
- program.
-
- A friend once told me of working as a programmer in a bank for about
- six months, writing a program similar to something that was commercially
- available. She believed that if she could have gotten source code for
- that commercially available program, it could easily have been adapted
- to their needs. The bank was willing to pay for this, but was not
- permitted to--the source code was a secret. So she had to do six
- months of make-work, work that counts in the GNP but was actually waste.
-
- The MIT Artificial Intelligence lab (AI lab) received a graphics
- printer as a gift from Xerox around 1977. It was run by free software
- to which we added many convenient features. For example, the software
- would notify a user immediately on completion of a print job. Whenever
- the printer had trouble, such as a paper jam or running out of paper,
- the software would immediately notify all users who had print jobs
- queued. These features facilitated smooth operation.
-
- Later Xerox gave the AI lab a newer, faster printer, one of the first
- laser printers. It was driven by proprietary software that ran in a
- separate dedicated computer, so we couldn't add any of our favorite
- features. We could arrange to send a notification when a print job was
- sent to the dedicated computer, but not when the job was actually
- printed (and the delay was usually considerable). There was no way to
- find out when the job was actually printed; you could only guess. And
- no one was informed when there was a paper jam, so the printer often
- went for an hour without being fixed.
-
- The system programmers at the AI lab were capable of fixing such
- problems, probably as capable as the original authors of the program.
- Xerox was uninterested in fixing them, and chose to prevent us, so we
- were forced to accept the problems. They were never fixed.
-
- Most good programmers have experienced this frustration. The bank
- could afford to solve the problem by writing a new program from
- scratch, but a typical user, no matter how skilled, can only give up.
-
- Giving up causes psychosocial harm--to the spirit of self-reliance.
- It is demoralizing to live in a house that you cannot rearrange to suit
- your needs. It leads to resignation and discouragement, which can
- spread to affect other aspects of one's life. People who feel this way
- are unhappy and do not do good work.
-
- Imagine what it would be like if recipes were hoarded in the same
- fashion as software. You might say, "How do I change this recipe to
- take out the salt?", and the great chef would respond, "How dare you
- insult my recipe, the child of my brain and my palate, by trying to
- tamper with it? You don't have the judgment to change my recipe and
- make it work right!"
-
- "But my doctor says I'm not supposed to eat salt! What can I do?
- Will you take out the salt for me?"
-
- "I would be glad to do that; my fee is only $50,000." Since the
- owner has a monopoly on changes, the fee tends to be large. "However,
- right now I don't have time. I am busy with a commission to design a
- new recipe for ship's biscuit for the Navy Department. I might get
- around to you in about two years."
-
- Obstructing Software Development
- ================================
-
- The third level of material harm affects software development.
- Software development used to be an evolutionary process, where a person
- would take an existing program and rewrite parts of it for one new
- feature, and then another person would rewrite parts to add another
- feature; in some cases, this continued over a period of twenty years.
- Meanwhile, parts of the program would be "cannibalized" to form the
- beginnings of other programs.
-
- The existence of owners prevents this kind of evolution, making it
- necessary to start from scratch when developing a program. It also
- prevents new practitioners from studying existing programs to learn
- useful techniques or even how large programs can be structured.
-
- Owners also obstruct education. I have met bright students in
- computer science who have never seen the source code of a large
- program. They may be good at writing small programs, but they can't
- begin to learn the different skills of writing large ones if they can't
- see how others have done it.
-
- In any intellectual field, one can reach greater heights by standing
- on the shoulders of others. But that is no longer generally allowed in
- the software field--you can only stand on the shoulders of the other
- people *in your own company*.
-
- The associated psychosocial harm affects the spirit of scientific
- cooperation, which used to be so strong that scientists would cooperate
- even when their countries were at war. In this spirit, Japanese
- oceanographers abandoning their lab on an island in the Pacific
- carefully preserved their work for the invading U.S. Marines, and left a
- note asking them to take good care of it.
-
- Conflict for profit has destroyed what international conflict spared.
- Nowadays scientists in many fields don't publish enough in their papers
- to enable others to replicate the experiment. They publish only enough
- to let readers marvel at how much they were able to do. This is
- certainly true in computer science, where the source code for the
- programs reported on is usually secret.
-
- It Does Not Matter How Sharing Is Restricted
- ============================================
-
- I have been discussing the effects of preventing people from copying,
- changing and building on a program. I have not specified how this
- obstruction is carried out, because that doesn't affect the conclusion.
- Whether it is done by copy protection, or copyright, or licenses, or
- encryption, or ROM cards, or hardware serial numbers, if it *succeeds*
- in preventing use, it does harm.
-
- Users do consider some of these methods more obnoxious than others.
- I suggest that the methods most hated are those that accomplish their
- objective.
-
- Software Should be Free
- =======================
-
- I have shown how ownership of a program--the power to restrict
- changing or copying it--is obstructive. Its negative effects are
- widespread and important. It follows that society shouldn't have
- owners for programs.
-
- Another way to understand this is that what society needs is free
- software, and proprietary software is a poor substitute. Encouraging
- the substitute is not a rational way to get what we need.
-
- Vaclav Havel has advised us to "Work for something because it is
- good, not just because it stands a chance to succeed." A business
- making proprietary software stands a chance of success in its own narrow
- terms, but it is not what is good for society.
-
- Why People Will Develop Software
- ********************************
-
- If we eliminate intellectual property as a means of encouraging
- people to develop software, at first less software will be developed,
- but that software will be more useful. It is not clear whether the
- overall delivered user satisfaction will be less; but if it is, or if
- we wish to increase it anyway, there are other ways to encourage
- development, just as there are ways besides toll booths to raise money
- for streets. Before I talk about how that can be done, first I want to
- question how much artificial encouragement is truly necessary.
-
- Programming is Fun
- ==================
-
- There are some lines of work that few will enter except for money;
- road construction, for example. There are other fields of study and
- art in which there is little chance to become rich, which people enter
- for their fascination or their perceived value to society. Examples
- include mathematical logic, classical music, and archaeology; and
- political organizing among working people. People compete, more sadly
- than bitterly, for the few funded positions available, none of which is
- funded very well. They may even pay for the chance to work in the
- field, if they can afford to.
-
- Such a field can transform itself overnight if it begins to offer the
- possibility of getting rich. When one worker gets rich, others demand
- the same opportunity. Soon all may demand large sums of money for doing
- what they used to do for pleasure. When another couple of years go by,
- everyone connected with the field will deride the idea that work would
- be done in the field without large financial returns. They will advise
- social planners to ensure that these returns are possible, prescribing
- special privileges, powers and monopolies as necessary to do so.
-
- This change happened in the field of computer programming in the past
- decade. Fifteen years ago, there were articles on "computer
- addiction": users were "onlining" and had hundred-dollar-a-week habits.
- It was generally understood that people frequently loved programming
- enough to break up their marriages. Today, it is generally understood
- that no one would program except for a high rate of pay. People have
- forgotten what they knew fifteen years ago.
-
- When it is true at a given time that most people will work in a
- certain field only for high pay, it need not remain true. The dynamic
- of change can run in reverse, if society provides an impetus. If we
- take away the possibility of great wealth, then after a while, when the
- people have readjusted their attitudes, they will once again be eager
- to work in the field for the joy of accomplishment.
-
- The question, "How can we pay programmers?", becomes an easier
- question when we realize that it's not a matter of paying them a
- fortune. A mere living is easier to raise.
-
- Funding Free Software
- =====================
-
- Institutions that pay programmers do not have to be software houses.
- Many other institutions already exist which can do this.
-
- Hardware manufacturers find it essential to support software
- development even if they cannot control the use of the software. In
- 1970, much of their software was free because they did not consider
- restricting it. Today, their increasing willingness to join
- consortiums shows their realization that owning the software is not
- what is really important for them.
-
- Universities conduct many programming projects. Today, they often
- sell the results, but in the 1970s, they did not. Is there any doubt
- that universities would develop free software if they were not allowed
- to sell software? These projects could be supported by the same
- government contracts and grants which now support proprietary software
- development.
-
- It is common today for university researchers to get grants to
- develop a system, develop it nearly to the point of completion and call
- that "finished", and then start companies where they really finish the
- project and make it usable. Sometimes they declare the unfinished
- version "free"; if they are thoroughly corrupt, they instead get an
- exclusive license from the university. This is not a secret; it is
- openly admitted by everyone concerned. Yet if the researchers were not
- exposed to the temptation to do these things, they would still do their
- research.
-
- Programmers writing free software can make their living by selling
- services related to the software. I have been hired to port the GNU C
- compiler to new hardware, and to make user-interface extensions to GNU
- Emacs. (I offer these improvements to the public once they are done.)
- I also teach classes for which I am paid.
-
- I am not alone in working this way; there is now a successful,
- growing corporation which does no other kind of work. Several other
- companies also provide commercial support for the free software of the
- GNU system. This is the beginning of the independent software support
- industry-an industry that could become quite large if free software
- becomes prevalent. It provides users with an option generally
- unavailable for proprietary software, except to the very wealthy.
-
- New institutions such as the Free Software Foundation can also fund
- programmers. Most of the foundation's funds come from users buying
- tapes through the mail. The software on the tapes is free, which means
- that every user has the freedom to copy it and change it, but many
- nonetheless pay to get copies. (Recall that "free software" refers to
- freedom, not to price.) Some users order tapes who already have a copy,
- as a way of making a contribution they feel we deserve. The Foundation
- also receives sizable donations from computer manufacturers.
-
- The Free Software Foundation is a charity, and its income is spent on
- hiring as many programmers as possible. If it had been set up as a
- business, distributing the same free software to the public for the same
- fee, it would now provide a very good living for its founder.
-
- Because the Foundation is a charity, programmers often work for the
- Foundation for half of what they could make elsewhere. They do this
- because we are free of bureaucracy, and because they feel satisfaction
- in knowing that their work will not be obstructed from use. Most of
- all, they do it because programming is fun. In addition, volunteers
- have written many useful programs for us. (Recently even technical
- writers have begun to volunteer.)
-
- This confirms that programming is among the most fascinating of all
- fields, along with music and art. We don't have to fear that no one
- will want to program.
-
- What Do Users Owe to Developers?
- ================================
-
- There is a good reason for users of software to feel a moral
- obligation to contribute to its support. Developers of free software
- are contributing to the users' activities, and it is both fair and in
- the long term interest of the users to give them funds to continue.
-
- However, this does not apply to proprietary software developers,
- since obstructionism deserves a punishment rather than a reward.
-
- We thus have a paradox: the developer of useful software is entitled
- to the support of the users, but any attempt to turn this moral
- obligation into a requirement destroys the basis for the obligation. A
- developer can either deserve a reward or demand it, but not both.
-
- I believe that an ethical developer faced with this paradox must act
- so as to deserve the reward, but should also entreat the users for
- voluntary donations. Eventually the users will learn to support
- developers without coercion, just as they have learned to support public
- radio and television stations.
-
- What Is Software Productivity?
- ******************************
-
- If software were free, there would still be programmers, but perhaps
- fewer of them. Would this be bad for society?
-
- Not necessarily. Today the advanced nations have fewer farmers than
- in 1900, but we do not think this is bad for society, because the few
- deliver more food to the consumers than the many used to do. We call
- this improved productivity. Free software would require far fewer
- programmers to satisfy the demand, because of increased software
- productivity at all levels:
-
- * Wider use of each program that is developed.
-
- * The ability to adapt existing programs for customization instead
- of starting from scratch.
-
- * Better education of programmers.
-
- * The elimination of duplicate development effort.
-
- Those who object to cooperation because it would result in the
- employment of fewer programmers, are actually objecting to increased
- productivity. Yet these people usually accept the widely-held belief
- that the software industry needs increased productivity. How is this?
-
- "Software productivity" can mean two different things: the overall
- productivity of all software development, or the productivity of
- individual projects. Overall productivity is what society would like to
- improve, and the most straightforward way to do this is to eliminate the
- artificial obstacles to cooperation which reduce it. But researchers
- who study the field of "software productivity" focus only on the
- second, limited, sense of the term, where improvement requires difficult
- technological advances.
-
- Is Competition Inevitable?
- **************************
-
- Is it inevitable that people will try to compete, to surpass their
- rivals in society? Perhaps it is. But competition itself is not
- harmful; the harmful thing is *combat*.
-
- There are many ways to compete. Competition can consist of trying to
- achieve ever more, to outdo what others have done. For example, in the
- old days, there was competition among programming wizards--competition
- for who could make the computer do the most amazing thing, or for who
- could make the shortest or fastest program for a given task. This kind
- of competition can benefit everyone, *as long as* the spirit of good
- sportsmanship is maintained.
-
- Constructive competition is enough competition to motivate people to
- great efforts. A number of people are competing to be the first to have
- visited all the countries on Earth; some even spend fortunes trying to
- do this. But they do not bribe ship captains to strand their rivals on
- desert islands. They are content to let the best person win.
-
- Competition becomes combat when the competitors begin trying to
- impede each other instead of advancing themselves--when "Let the best
- person win" gives way to "Let me win, best or not." Proprietary
- software is harmful, not because it is a form of competition, but
- because it is a form of combat among the citizens of our society.
-
- Competition in business is not necessarily combat. For example, when
- two grocery stores compete, their entire effort is to improve their own
- operations, not to sabotage the rival. But this does not demonstrate a
- special commitment to business ethics; rather, there is little scope for
- combat in this line of business short of physical violence. Not all
- areas of business share this characteristic. Withholding information
- that could help everyone advance is a form of combat.
-
- Business ideology does not prepare people to resist the temptation to
- combat the competition. Some forms of combat have been made banned with
- anti-trust laws, truth in advertising laws, and so on, but rather than
- generalizing this to a principled rejection of combat in general,
- executives invent other forms of combat which are not specifically
- prohibited. Society's resources are squandered on the economic
- equivalent of factional civil war.
-
- "Why Don't You Move to Russia?"
- *******************************
-
- In the United States, any advocate of other than the most extreme
- form of laissez-faire selfishness has often heard this accusation. For
- example, it is leveled against the supporters of a national health care
- system, such as is found in all the other industrialized nations of the
- free world. It is leveled against the advocates of public support for
- the arts, also universal in advanced nations. The idea that citizens
- have any obligation to the public good is identified in America with
- Communism. But how similar are these ideas?
-
- Communism as was practiced in the Soviet Union was a system of
- central control where all activity was regimented, supposedly for the
- common good, but actually for the sake of the members of the Communist
- party. And where copying equipment was closely guarded to prevent
- illegal copying.
-
- The American system of intellectual property exercises central
- control over distribution of a program, and guards copying equipment
- with automatic copying protection schemes to prevent illegal copying.
-
- By contrast, I am working to build a system where people are free to
- decide their own actions; in particular, free to help their neighbors,
- and free to alter and improve the tools which they use in their daily
- lives. A system based on voluntary cooperation, and decentralization.
-
- Thus, if we are to judge views by their resemblance to Russian
- Communism, it is the software owners who are the Communists.
-
- The Question of Premises
- ************************
-
- I make the assumption in this paper that a user of software is no
- less important than an author, or even an author's employer. In other
- words, their interests and needs have equal weight, when we decide
- which course of action is best.
-
- This premise is not universally accepted. Many maintain that an
- author's employer is fundamentally more important than anyone else.
- They say, for example, that the purpose of having owners of software is
- to give the author's employer the advantage he deserves--regardless of
- how this may affect the public.
-
- It is no use trying to prove or disprove these premises. Proof
- requires shared premises. So most of what I have to say is addressed
- only to those who share the premises I use, or at least are interested
- in what their consequences are. For those who believe that the owners
- are more important than everyone else, this paper is simply irrelevant.
-
- But why would a large number of Americans accept a premise which
- elevates certain people in importance above everyone else? Partly
- because of the belief that this premise is part of the legal traditions
- of American society. Some people feel that doubting the premise means
- challenging the basis of society.
-
- It is important for these people to know that this premise is not
- part of our legal tradition. It never has been.
-
- Thus, the Constitution says that the purpose of copyright is to
- "promote the progress of science and the useful arts." The Supreme
- Court has elaborated on this, stating in `Fox Film vs. Doyal' that "The
- sole interest of the United States and the primary object in conferring
- the [copyright] monopoly lie in the general benefits derived by the
- public from the labors of authors."
-
- We are not required to agree with the Constitution or the Supreme
- Court. (At one time, they both condoned slavery.) So their positions
- do not disprove the owner supremacy premise. But I hope that the
- awareness that this is a radical right-wing assumption rather than a
- traditionally recognized one will weaken its appeal.
-
- Conclusion
- **********
-
- We like to think that our society encourages helping your neighbor;
- but each time we reward someone for obstructionism, or admire them for
- the wealth they have gained in this way, we are sending the opposite
- message.
-
- Software hoarding is one form of our general willingness to disregard
- the welfare of society for personal gain. We can trace this disregard
- from Ronald Reagan to Jim Bakker, from Ivan Boesky to Exxon, from
- failing banks to failing schools. We can measure it with the size of
- the homeless population and the prison population. The antisocial
- spirit feeds on itself, because the more we see that other people will
- not help us, the more it seems futile to help them. Thus society decays
- into a jungle.
-
- If we don't want to live in a jungle, we must change our attitudes.
- We must start sending the message that a good citizen is one who
- cooperates when appropriate, not one who is successful at taking from
- others. I hope that the free software movement will contribute to
- this: at least in one area, we will replace the jungle with a more
- efficient system which encourages and runs on voluntary cooperation.
-
- ---------- Footnotes ----------
-
- (1) The word "free" in "free software" refers to freedom, not to
- price; the price paid for a copy of a free program may be zero, or
- small, or (rarely) quite large.
-
- (2) The issues of pollution and traffic congestion do not alter
- this conclusion. If we wish to make driving more expensive to
- discourage driving in general, it is disadvantageous to do this using
- toll booths, which contribute to both pollution and congestion. A tax
- on gasoline is much better. Likewise, a desire to enhance safety by
- limiting maximum speed is not relevant; a free access road enhances the
- average speed by avoiding stops and delays, for any given speed limit.
-
- (3) One might regard a particular computer program as a harmful
- thing that should not be available at all, like the Lotus Marketplace
- database of personal information, which was withdrawn from sale due to
- public disapproval. Most of what I say does not apply to this case,
- but it makes little sense to argue for having an owner on the grounds
- that the owner will make the program less available. The owner will
- not make it *completely* unavailable, as one would wish in the case of
- a program whose use is considered destructive.
-
-